The Categories by Aristotle (which ebook reader .TXT) 📕
- Author: Aristotle
- Performer: -
Book online «The Categories by Aristotle (which ebook reader .TXT) 📕». Author Aristotle
stated as haphazard and not accurately, the two are not found to
be interdependent. Let me state what I mean more clearly. Even in
the case of acknowledged correlatives, and where names exist for
each, there will be no interdependence if one of the two is
denoted, not by that name which expresses the correlative notion,
but by one of irrelevant significance. The term ‘slave,’ if
defined as related, not to a master, but to a man, or a biped, or
anything of that sort, is not reciprocally connected with that in
relation to which it is defined, for the statement is not exact.
Further, if one thing is said to be correlative with another, and
the terminology used is correct, then, though all irrelevant
attributes should be removed, and only that one attribute left in
virtue of which it was correctly stated to be correlative with
that other, the stated correlation will still exist. If the
correlative of ‘the slave’ is said to be ‘the master’, then,
though all irrelevant attributes of the said ‘master’, such as
‘biped’, ‘receptive of knowledge’, ‘human’, should be removed,
and the attribute ‘master’ alone left, the stated correlation
existing between him and the slave will remain the same, for it
is of a master that a slave is said to be the slave. On the other
hand, if, of two correlatives, one is not correctly termed, then,
when all other attributes are removed and that alone is left in
virtue of which it was stated to be correlative, the stated
correlation will be found to have disappeared.
For suppose the correlative of ‘the slave’ should be said to be
‘the man’, or the correlative of ‘the wing”the bird’; if the
attribute ‘master’ be withdrawn from’ the man’, the correlation
between ‘the man’ and ‘the slave’ will cease to exist, for if the
man is not a master, the slave is not a slave. Similarly, if the
attribute ‘winged’ be withdrawn from ‘the bird’, ‘the wing’ will
no longer be relative; for if the so-called correlative is not
winged, it follows that ‘the wing’ has no correlative.
Thus it is essential that the correlated terms should be exactly
designated; if there is a name existing, the statement will be
easy; if not, it is doubtless our duty to construct names. When
the terminology is thus correct, it is evident that all
correlatives are interdependent.
Correlatives are thought to come into existence simultaneously.
This is for the most part true, as in the case of the double and
the half. The existence of the half necessitates the existence of
that of which it is a half. Similarly the existence of a master
necessitates the existence of a slave, and that of a slave
implies that of a master; these are merely instances of a general
rule. Moreover, they cancel one another; for if there is no
double it follows that there is no half, and vice versa; this
rule also applies to all such correlatives. Yet it does not
appear to be true in all cases that correlatives come into
existence simultaneously. The object of knowledge would appear to
exist before knowledge itself, for it is usually the case that we
acquire knowledge of objects already existing; it would be
difficult, if not impossible, to find a branch of knowledge the
beginning of the existence of which was contemporaneous with that
of its object.
Again, while the object of knowledge, if it ceases to exist,
cancels at the same time the knowledge which was its correlative,
the converse of this is not true. It is true that if the object
of knowledge does not exist there can be no knowledge: for there
will no longer be anything to know. Yet it is equally true that,
if knowledge of a certain object does not exist, the object may
nevertheless quite well exist. Thus, in the case of the squaring
of the circle, if indeed that process is an object of knowledge,
though it itself exists as an object of knowledge, yet the
knowledge of it has not yet come into existence. Again, if all
animals ceased to exist, there would be no knowledge, but there
might yet be many objects of knowledge.
This is likewise the case with regard to perception: for the
object of perception is, it appears, prior to the act of
perception. If the perceptible is annihilated, perception also
will cease to exist; but the annihilation of perception does not
cancel the existence of the perceptible. For perception implies a
body perceived and a body in which perception takes place. Now if
that which is perceptible is annihilated, it follows that the
body is annihilated, for the body is a perceptible thing; and if
the body does not exist, it follows that perception also ceases
to exist. Thus the annihilation of the perceptible involves that
of perception.
But the annihilation of perception does not involve that of the
perceptible. For if the animal is annihilated, it follows that
perception also is annihilated, but perceptibles such as body,
heat, sweetness, bitterness, and so on, will remain.
Again, perception is generated at the same time as the perceiving
subject, for it comes into existence at the same time as the
animal. But the perceptible surely exists before perception; for
fire and water and such elements, out of which the animal is
itself composed, exist before the animal is an animal at all, and
before perception. Thus it would seem that the perceptible exists
before perception.
It may be questioned whether it is true that no substance is
relative, as seems to be the case, or whether exception is to be
made in the case of certain secondary substances. With regard to
primary substances, it is quite true that there is no such
possibility, for neither wholes nor parts of primary substances
are relative. The individual man or ox is not defined with
reference to something external. Similarly with the parts: a
particular hand or head is not defined as a particular hand or
head of a particular person, but as the hand or head of a
particular person. It is true also, for the most part at least,
in the case of secondary substances; the species ‘man’ and the
species ‘ox’ are not defined with reference to anything outside
themselves. Wood, again, is only relative in so far as it is some
one’s property, not in so far as it is wood. It is plain, then,
that in the cases mentioned substance is not relative. But with
regard to some secondary substances there is a difference of
opinion; thus, such terms as ‘head’ and ‘hand’ are defined with
reference to that of which the things indicated are a part, and
so it comes about that these appear to have a relative character.
Indeed, if our definition of that which is relative was complete,
it is very difficult, if not impossible, to prove that no
substance is relative. If, however, our definition was not
complete, if those things only are properly called relative in
the case of which relation to an external object is a necessary
condition of existence, perhaps some explanation of the dilemma
may be found.
The former definition does indeed apply to all relatives, but the
fact that a thing is explained with reference to something else
does not make it essentially relative.
>From this it is plain that, if a man definitely apprehends a
relative thing, he will also definitely apprehend that to which
it is relative. Indeed this is self-evident: for if a man knows
that some particular thing is relative, assuming that we call
that a relative in the case of which relation to something is a
necessary condition of existence, he knows that also to which it
is related. For if he does not know at all that to which it is
related, he will not know whether or not it is relative. This is
clear, moreover, in particular instances. If a man knows
definitely that such and such a thing is ‘double’, he will also
forthwith know definitely that of which it is the double. For if
there is nothing definite of which he knows it to be the double,
he does not know at all that it is double. Again, if he knows
that a thing is more beautiful, it follows necessarily that he
will forthwith definitely know that also than which it is more
beautiful. He will not merely know indefinitely that it is more
beautiful than something which is less beautiful, for this would
be supposition, not knowledge. For if he does not know definitely
that than which it is more beautiful, he can no longer claim to
know definitely that it is more beautiful than something else
which is less beautiful: for it might be that nothing was less
beautiful. It is, therefore, evident that if a man apprehends
some relative thing definitely, he necessarily knows that also
definitely to which it is related.
Now the head, the hand, and such things are substances, and it is
possible to know their essential character definitely, but it
does not necessarily follow that we should know that to which
they are related. It is not possible to know forthwith whose head
or hand is meant. Thus these are not relatives, and, this being
the case, it would be true to say that no substance is relative
in character. It is perhaps a difficult matter, in such cases, to
make a positive statement without more exhaustive examination,
but to have raised questions with regard to details is not
without advantage.
By ‘quality’ I mean that in virtue of which people are said to be
such and such.
Quality is a term that is used in many senses. One sort of
quality let us call ‘habit’ or ‘disposition’. Habit differs from
disposition in being more lasting and more firmly established.
The various kinds of knowledge and of virtue are habits, for
knowledge, even when acquired only in a moderate degree, is, it
is agreed, abiding in its character and difficult to displace,
unless some great mental upheaval takes place, through disease or
any such cause. The virtues, also, such as justice,
self-restraint, and so on, are not easily dislodged or dismissed,
so as to give place to vice.
By a disposition, on the other hand, we mean a condition that is
easily changed and quickly gives place to its opposite. Thus,
heat, cold, disease, health, and so on are dispositions. For a
man is disposed in one way or another with reference to these,
but quickly changes, becoming cold instead of warm, ill instead
of well. So it is with all other dispositions also, unless
through lapse of time a disposition has itself become inveterate
and almost impossible to dislodge: in which case we should
perhaps go so far as to call it a habit.
It is evident that men incline to call those conditions habits
which are of a more or less permanent type and difficult to
displace; for those who are not retentive of knowledge, but
volatile, are not said to have such and such a ‘habit’ as regards
knowledge, yet they are disposed, we may say, either better or
worse, towards knowledge. Thus habit differs from disposition in
this, that while the latter in ephemeral, the former is permanent
and difficult to alter.
Habits are at the same time dispositions, but dispositions are
not necessarily habits. For those who have some specific habit
may be said also, in virtue of that habit, to be thus or thus
disposed; but those who are disposed in some specific way have
not in all cases the corresponding habit.
Another sort of quality is that in virtue of which, for example,
we call men good boxers or runners, or healthy
Comments (0)